Please call to schedule your free initial consultation: 403.262.1110|melanie@yycdefence.ca

Appeal Lawyers Calgary

Sitar & Milczarek

Criminal Appeals & Complex Trials

The Defence Toolkit – August 2, 2025: Diminished Moral Blameworthiness

Posted On 2 August 2025

This week’s top three summaries: R v IM, 2025 SCC 23: YCJA adult #sentences, R v Stewart, 2025 NSCA 57: #blackout & consent, R v Rashed, 2025 ONCA 515: #accessory wilful blindness

R v IM, 2025 SCC 23

[July 18, 2025] Youth Criminal Justice Act sentencing: Adult Sentences under s.72 [Reasons by Kasirer J. with Wagner C.J., Karakatsanis, Martin, Jamal, O’Bonsawin, and Moreau JJ. concurring, Dissenting: Côté and Rowe JJ.]

AUTHOR’S NOTE: In this decision, the Supreme Court of Canada clarifies the test and burden of proof that applies when the Crown seeks an adult sentence for a young person under the Youth Criminal Justice Act (YCJA)—that is, an individual between the ages of 12 and 17 at the time of the offence.

The Court confirmed that there is a two-part test, and in both parts, the Crown bears the burden of proof beyond a reasonable doubt:

  1. Rebutting the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness:
    The YCJA presumes that young persons have diminished moral blameworthiness due to their developmental immaturity. To rebut this presumption, the Crown must present evidence specifically addressing the young person’s developmental age, including their maturity, independence, and capacity for moral reasoning.
    Crucially, the seriousness or gravity of the offence is not relevant to this part of the test—it cannot substitute for an individualized assessment of moral culpability.

  2. Establishing that a youth sentence would not hold the young person accountable:
    If the presumption is rebutted, the Crown must then prove that a youth sentence would be insufficient to hold the young person accountable for their actions. This analysis still takes place within the framework of YCJA sentencing principles, which prioritize rehabilitation and reintegration while also considering accountability, proportionality, and the protection of the public.

This decision reinforces that adult sentencing is exceptional under the YCJA, and that developmental context must be central to any determination of moral blameworthiness and appropriate accountability for youth.


I. Overview

[1] When I.M. was 17 years and 5 months old, he and several others confronted S.T., another 17-year-old, in an alley. The group sought to rob S.T. who they believed was in possession of firearms. S.T. died as a result of knife wounds sustained in the fray. I.M. was convicted of first degree murder by a youth justice court. The Crown sought an order that he receive an adult sentence. The sentencing judge was satisfied that the requirements for an adult sentence order were met, and he sentenced I.M. to life in prison without eligibility for parole before 10 years. The Court of Appeal dismissed I.M.’s appeal. Before this Court, I.M. says the courts below erred in their interpretation of s. 72(1) of the Youth Criminal Justice Act, S.C. 2002, c. 1 (“YCJA”), and those errors in law had a material effect on his sentence. I.M. asks that a youth sentence be imposed in place of the adult sentence of life imprisonment.

[3] The regime for sentencing under the YCJA, like that under the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46 (“Cr. C.”), applicable to adults, endeavours to hold young persons accountable for their offending conduct through the imposition of sanctions with “meaningful consequences”. But the YCJA does so in a separate system for criminal justice based on “the principle of diminished moral blameworthiness or culpability” (s. 3(1)(b) YCJA). Thus, a youth sentence for first degree murder cannot exceed a period of 10 years, comprised of a committal to custody of no more than 6 years and a placement under conditional supervision in the community (s. 42(2)(q)(i) YCJA). By contrast, the applicable adult sentence for the same offence is life imprisonment, without possibility of parole for 10 years (ss. 235(1) and 745.1(b) Cr. C.).

[4] There is no doubt that the onus of convincing the youth justice court that an adult sentence should be ordered is on the Crown (s. 72(2) YCJA). Section 72(1) YCJA sets out what the Crown must prove. An adult sentence shall be ordered when the youth justice court is satisfied that the “presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness or culpability” of the young person is rebutted and when a youth sentence would not be of sufficient length to “hold the young person accountable” for their offending conduct….

[6]….When an individual is under 18 — when they are a “young person” according to the definition in s. 2(1) YCJA — they are entitled to the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness in s. 72(1)(a) by virtue of theirchronological age. However, when a young person is shown by the Crown to have the maturity of an adult, they lose the benefit of the presumption that would otherwise mean, because of their age, that they receive a youth sentence under the YCJA. Like the presumption itself, rebuttal of the presumption by the Crown therefore rests on proof of a fact: when the young person’s developmental age, contrary to their chronological age, indicates they have the capacity for moral judgment of an adult, the young person is no longer deserving of the presumption’s benefit. Proving that a young person has the developmental age of an adult may of course be more complicated than proving chronological age, but it is no less a factual inquiry that lends itself just as well to proof beyond a reasonable doubt.

[7] Importantly, the rule on rebutting the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness in s. 72(1) YCJA must be read, if its meaning is uncertain, in a manner that conforms to the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. The Court has decided that there is a principle of fundamental justice under s. 7 of the Charter that young persons are entitled to a presumption of diminished culpability in sentencing (R. v. D.B., 2008 SCC 25, [2008] 2 S.C.R. 3, at paras. 69-70)….

….In the law of sentencing, this Court’s jurisprudence makes plain that facts that tend to aggravate a sentence must be proved beyond a reasonable doubt as a matter of fundamental justice under the Charter (paras. 78-80, citing R. v. Pearson, [1992] 3 S.C.R. 665, at p. 686, and R. v. Gardiner, [1982] 2 S.C.R. 368, at pp. 414-15).

[8] If the presumption is rebutted, I.M.’s jeopardy is substantially increased in that he faces the adult sentence of life imprisonment for murder as against a youth sentence that cannot exceed 10 years. The Crown must show that, notwithstanding the fact that I.M. was a young person at the time of the offence, his developmental age at that time was that of an adult. This must be done on a standard of beyond a reasonable doubt given that rebutting the presumption amounts to proving an aggravating factor. This is because rebuttal exposes I.M. to the risk of a sentence that is significantly more severe than the youth sentence applicable to first degree murder.[Emphasis by PJM]

[10] Courts have also disagreed on what factors a sentencing judge should consider in determining whether the Crown has successfully rebutted the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness. The seriousness or objective gravity of the offence, for example, while relevant at the second stage of the analysis under s. 72(1)(b) YCJA, has no logical bearing on the determination of whether a young person displays the capacity for moral judgment of an adult at the time of the offence. As such, it is irrelevant to rebutting the presumption in s. 72(1)(a). At the same time, factors that properly fix on the young offender’s developmental age and capacity for moral judgment, such as their mental health and background, need to be considered where they are part of the record.[Emphasis by PJM]

[11] If the presumption is rebutted by the Crown under s. 72(1)(a), a second and distinct requirement must be met before an adult sentence can be ordered. Under s. 72(1)(b), the sentencing judge must be satisfied that a youth sentence would be insufficient to hold the young person accountable for the offence.

[12] The Crown again bears the onus to show that the youth sentence — in this case the one that is set out in s. 42(2)(q)(i) YCJA — would be unfit, but the standard of satisfaction is not beyond a reasonable doubt. Here the nature of the inquiry resembles the determination of a fit sentence, an evaluative inquiry involving a discretionary weighing of aggravating and mitigating circumstances relating to the offence and the offender and the balance of competing sentencing principles (see B.J.M., at para. 95).[Emphasis by PJM]

[13] At this stage, the seriousness of the offence is most germane, in that the exercise includes a consideration of whether a youth sentence is proportionate to the gravity of the offence and the degree of responsibility of the offender. The profile and background of the offender may again be relevant, but to a different end. At this stage, these matters are not considered in respect of the rationale engaged by the presumption in s. 72(1)(a) relating to the capacity for moral judgment but, instead, to the rationale of accountability to which Parliament speaks in s. 72(1)(b).

[14] In the case of I.M., and with respect for other views, I conclude that the Crown has not shown beyond a reasonable doubt that the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness has been rebutted at the first threshold step in s. 72(1)(a). The sentencing judge applied the wrong standard to testing the Crown’s onus. The court then considered, as a factor in the calculus, the seriousness of the offence which was a further error of law in that it is not relevant to the inquiry under s. 72(1)(a).

[15] In addition, the sentencing judge did not properly consider aspects of I.M.’s medical history, as revealed by expert medical evidence, and his personal background. Moreover, implications of some of the facts found by the sentencing judge showed I.M.’s immaturity and lack of adult-like capacity for moral judgment at the time of the offence. These matters presented a further obstacle to rebutting the presumption. These errors had the cumulative effect of undermining the sentence which, following the standard of review explained in R. v. Lacasse, 2015 SCC 64, [2015] 3 S.C.R. 1089, at paras. 44 et seq., is not deserving of deference on appeal.

[16] In the circumstances, this Court must intervene and conduct its own sentencing analysis (Lacasse, at para. 43; R. v. Friesen, 2020 SCC 9, [2020] 1 S.C.R. 424, at para. 27)….

….Accepting the sentencing judge’s findings of fact, including those arrived at in respect of the circumstances of the offence, there was evidence before the youth court of I.M.’s difficult upbringing and mental health problems affecting his developmental age relevant to s. 72(1)(a), and demonstrating that his level of maturity was not that of an adult at the time of the offence. Furthermore, the evidence accepted by the sentencing judge also showed that, at the time of the offence, I.M. saw his own conduct in the robbery as an occasion to prove his worth to adult peers as a criminal. Four days after the event, I.M. also imprudently recounted his wrongful conduct to a schoolmate. These facts were not just proof of I.M.’s involvement in the crime, as the sentencing judge rightly noted, but also reflected signs of incautious bravado, lack of adult-like reasoning and I.M.’s immature susceptibility to untoward adult influence at the time of the offence.

[18]  For the reasons that follow, I would allow the appeal, set aside the judgment of the Court of Appeal, quash the youth justice court’s decision, and sentence I.M. afresh as a young person under s. 42(2) YCJA. I hasten to say that, I.M. remains no less accountable at sentencing for the offence he committed in 2011 as a young person….

A. The Two Prongs of Section 72(1) Should Be Considered Separately

[85] I agree with I.M. that s. 72(1) creates a two-pronged onus for the Crown and that sentencing judges should engage separately with the inquiries under s. 72(1). This is the most natural reading of the text of the provision. Considering the grammatical and ordinary meaning of s. 72(1), the words and structure of the provision suggest that Parliament intended these inquiries to be treated separately. In the English version, the two prongs are set out in independent paragraphs and are separated by the conjunction “and”, suggesting that there are two inquiries. It is also implicit in the phrasing and structure of the French version that both prongs must be independently satisfied. Furthermore, the ordinary meaning of the words in each paragraph indicates that the inquiries are different in nature. While the first paragraph requires the court to be satisfied the Crown has rebutted the “presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness” — a concept that is not defined in the statute — and sets out no other criteria, the second directs the court to consider specific provisions of the YCJA setting out the purpose and principles of sentencing in assessing the issue of accountability. The presumption is also listed as the first requirement, suggesting it is indeed a threshold consideration.

[87] ….Under the current s. 72(1), the Crown now has the burden to prove that a youth sentence is insufficient to hold the offender accountable. In addition, Parliament added the first prong, requiring the Crown to rebut the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness. This interpretation is consistent with the broader context of the provision.

[88] ….Since the presumption must be rebutted for an adult sentence to be compliant with the Charter (paras. 70 and 76-78), a test with two separate prongs ensures that the presumption is given constitutional force by being assessed independently, before further consideration is given to whether a youth sentence would be of sufficient length to hold the young person accountable. I agree with the view that the blended approach to ss. 72(1)(a) and 72(1)(b) called for by the Crown flies in the face of the text of the provision which separates the two prongs; it fails to take account of the context and purpose of the YCJA that enshrines, distinct from accountability, the general principle of diminished moral culpability of young persons enshrined in s. 3(1)(b). And practically speaking, it is unworkable in that it would bring irrelevant factors such as seriousness of the offence into the evaluation of the applicability of the presumption, thereby distorting the analysis required of sentencing judges under s. 72(1)(a) (see Henderson, at para. 38).

[89] ….As Epstein J.A. observed in W. (M.), the YCJA recognizes young people as “constitutionally different” from adults for sentencing purposes (para. 163; see also R. v. Chol, 2018 BCCA 179, at para. 38; Okemow, at para. 52). As I will explain below, rebutting the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness must therefore depend on the personal attributes of the offender that speak to their developmental age, rather than any objective assessments of fault that may flow from the offence at issue. To rebut the presumption, then, the sentencing judge must determine whether the young person’s presumed diminished moral blameworthiness is contradicted by their actual personal attributes. As I seek to explain further below, this is a factual question that ultimately asks whether, at the time of the offence, the developmental age of the young offender was akin to that of an adult.

B. Rebutting the Presumption of Diminished Moral Blameworthiness (Section 72(1)(a))

(1) The Presumption as a Principle of Fundamental Justice

[96] When a young person is sentenced, the separate regime of the YCJA applies because the offender is presumed to have diminished moral blameworthiness based on their chronological age. In D.B., this Court recognized the presumption as a principle of fundamental justice protected by s. 7 of the Charter (para. 76). Section 72(1) YCJA was subsequently amended to codify this principle, which was also enacted as a guiding principle for the whole of the YCJA in s. 3(1). In interpreting s. 72, this Court must determine how the Crown goes about meeting its onus to rebut the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness that would otherwise justify a youth sentence.

[100] ….Drawing on s. 7’s residual protection for the presumption of innocence, Abella J. recognized the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness as a principle of fundamental justice under s. 7 of the Charter (paras. 45-69 and 80), and held that the onus provisions in the presumptive offences regime unjustifiably violated s. 7 of the Charter. The Court found that imposing the burden on young offenders to rebut the presumption of an adult sentence undermined the central premise of the youth justice system: that young people are less morally culpable than adults due to their developmental immaturity (D.B., at paras. 66 and 68).

[102] While the presumption is rebuttable, s. 72(1)(a) imposes on the Crown a heavy onus to justify the imposition of an adult sentence given its status as a principle of fundamental justice as recognized by the Court in D.B. (paras. 45 and 68)….

(2) The Crown Must Prove That the Developmental Age of the Young Person Is That of an Adult

[104] As we shall see, the jurisprudence and scholarly commentary in youth matters have recognized that adult-like maturity and the capacity for moral judgment develop over time, echoing an idea Parliament gave voice to in the opening paragraph of the preamble to the YCJA: that “members of society share a responsibility to address the developmental challenges and the needs of young persons and to guide them into adulthood”. This Court’s judgment in D.B. recognized, at para. 62, that while age plays a role in the development of judgment and moral sophistication, chronological age and maturity may not be one and the same. In connection with the rebuttal of the presumption, it is important to note that a young person’s developmental maturity does not necessarily coincide with their chronological age.

[108] In other words, since developmental age underlies a young person’s presumed diminished blameworthiness, it must be the focus of the inquiry on an application to impose an adult sentence to remove the protection afforded by the presumption. Just as the presumption rests on a clear factual basis of chronological age, developmental age is similarly a factual inquiry, even if it is perhaps less straightforward. The Crown’s onus is not merely a procedural protection, as the Crown emphasizes (R.F., at para. 97), but a substantive protection. As I will explain, it requires the Crown to satisfy the court that the young offender’s developmental profile is inconsistent with that presumed of a typical youth — that they possess adult-like maturity, capacity for moral judgment, and independence (D.B., at paras. 41-47; see also Parkes, at pp. 12-14).[Emphasis by PJM]

[111] ….Expanding on W. (M.), in Chol, Stromberg-Stein J.A. articulated a non-exhaustive list of factors that could be relevant to the inquiry, including the young person’s independence or dependence on others, cognitive limitations, emotional or mental health issues, the maturity or immaturity of the reasoning behind the motive of the offence, and whether the actions demonstrated critical and adult-like judgment (para. 61).

(3) The Standard of Proof To Meet the Crown’s Onus To Rebut the Presumption Is Beyond a Reasonable Doubt

[117] As I will explain, I agree with the appellant. In my view, the Crown must rebut the presumption beyond a reasonable doubt as the inquiry under s. 72(1)(a) is factual in nature and can expose the young person to a more severe sentence.

(4) The Factors Relevant to the Crown’s Onus When Rebutting the Presumption

[131] ….This exercise is undertaken by considering factors that provide insight into the young offender’s personal developmental attributes at the time of the offence. This assessment is inherently fact-specific, nuanced, and contextual (see Chol, at para. 60). While it cannot be reduced to a rigid formula or checklist, the circumstances of the offender or evidence that speaks to the developmental age of the young person at the time of the offence will be most relevant (see D.B., at para. 41; W. (M.), at para. 98; Okemow, at para. 62; Chol, at paras. 43 and 61).

[132] Factors that speak to the offence, rather than the young offender, are beyond the scope of this inquiry unless they show something about the offender’s personal attributes reflecting their developmental age.

(a) Seriousness of the Offence Is Not Relevant to the Presumption

[135] I agree that courts should not weigh the objective seriousness of the offence in determining whether the Crown has rebutted the presumption, although not every abstract reference to seriousness will necessarily be an error. Moreover, the circumstances of the offence may be relevant if they clarify the youth’s developmental age at the time of the offence. I first address this issue before turning to other factors.

[140] ….In my view, factors that speak to the objective gravity of the offence, rather than the young offender, are irrelevant to this inquiry as they would not shed light on the offender’s developmental attributes.

[142] Consideration and weighing of the objective seriousness of an offence as a factor under the presumption is therefore an error in principle. However, I note that not every reference to objective gravity or seriousness will result in a reviewable error if it is plain that it did not impact the sentencing judge’s conclusion on the presumption and that the judge was focused on developmental age.

[143] ….While the factual circumstances of an offence may provide insight into an offender’s developmental age relevant to the first prong, they do not alter the offence’s inherent gravity (see para. 76; R. v. Hills, 2023 SCC 2, at para. 58). Maintaining this distinction ensures that s. 72(1)(a) remains focused on the young person’s developmental maturity rather than the objective gravity of the offence. A violent crime, however serious in character, tragic in consequence or troubling in execution, is not inherently indicative of a young person with the developmental age of an adult.

[145] In contrast with the objective seriousness of the offence, the circumstances of the offence may be a relevant consideration under the first prong of s. 72(1)(a), but only insofar as they offer insights into the young person’s developmental age….

[146] ….Courts must therefore exercise caution: the violent character of the commission of a crime, while relevant — like the seriousness of the offence — to the young person’s accountability under s. 72(1)(b), may not always carry relevant information to rebutting the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness. Young persons may commit violent crimes in grim circumstances impulsively or to impress others, in ways that reflect a diminished capacity for adult-like judgment….

[147] Relevant considerations under s. 72(1)(a) may include whether the conduct is consistent with the presumed lesser maturity of the young offender, such as impulsiveness or bravado (R. v. A.M., 2024 ONSC 5323, at paras. 62-64). A young person’s impulsive reaction in the course of committing an offence can reflect a sense of invincibility that indicates immaturity, while deliberate planning may suggest more advanced moral and cognitive development as it may demonstrate that they engaged in critical thinking, considered planning, adult-like judgment, or demonstrated an understanding of the consequences of their actions (Chol, at para. 61). Yet, as noted by the intervener Justice for Children and Youth, even young offenders are capable of some degree of planning and deliberation. The focus must remain on whether the offender’s planning, combined with other considerations, reveals a level of sophistication and foresight that aligns with adult-level reasoning, rather than merely identifying the presence of planning.

[148] Similarly, a young offender’s post-offence conduct — that is, after-the-fact conduct temporally linked and related to the offence at issue — may be potentially informative, but warrants some caution in its consideration. I agree with the Court of Appeal that post-offence conduct may demonstrate a “level of maturity, moral sophistication, and capacity for independent judgement” (para. 81, citing W. (M.), at para. 98). Certain types of post-offence conduct — such as attempts to evade detection, destroy evidence, or mitigate the harm — may, depending on the case, suggest sophistication and capacity to form moral judgment.

[149] However, such conduct can also reflect impulsive reactions driven by juvenile fear and panic, rather than adult-like calculation (Chol, at para. 61). Post-offence conduct must be examined in context to avoid misinterpretation or overemphasis. The overarching question is whether the circumstances of the offence shed light on the offender’s developmental age in light of their broader personal attributes.(b) Factors Related to Personal Circumstances of the Offender.

(b) Factors Related to Personal Circumstances of the Offender

[151] Personal circumstances of the offender relevant to rebutting the presumption will be individualized, offender-centric evidence that the young person’s developmental age is akin to that of an adult. This may include the young person’s actual age, background, sophistication in thinking, capacity for independent judgment, behaviour after the offence, whether the person was living like an adult, cognitive, emotional and mental health, and susceptibility to external influences among others (Chol, at para. 61; W. (M.), at para. 98; R.D.F., at para. 37; C. C. Ruby, Sentencing (10th ed. 2020), at §22.48).

[152] An offender’s chronological age is an important personal attribute, as it helps anchor further developmental considerations. However, age is only one factor, and it cannot eclipse other indicators of the young offender’s developmental age as a matter of course (see A.M., at paras. 65-66)….

[153] It may well be true, as a common-sense generalization, that a young person very near to their 18th birthday will likely be more mature than, say, a 14- or 15-year-old in respect of whom s. 64 YCJA adult sentencing applications may also be brought. By the same token, common-sense generalizations about the maturity of 14-year-old offenders compared to those who are on the cusp of 18 may fairly suggest that the 14-year-old is less likely to have the developmental age of an adult. In all cases, however, fixing developmental age remains an individualized factual determination that cannot be cut short by a common-sense generalization based on chronological age that is insufficiently sensitive to the offender’s particular circumstances.

[155] Evidence of cognitive and emotional limitations, including behavioural disorders or mental health issues may also assist sentencing judges when determining the young offender’s developmental age. These factors do not excuse criminal conduct but may demonstrate the young person’s presumed vulnerability, reduced maturity and reduced ability to exercise independent judgment and capacity to make rational, informed decisions at the time of the offence (see R.D.F., at para. 37; Chol, at para. 61; R. v. Z.A., [2023] EWCA Crim 596, [2023] 2 Cr. App. R. (S.) 45 (p. 404), at para. 52; on cognitive trauma in young persons more generally, see also R. v. Brown, [2013] NICA 5, at para. 7; Bugmy v. The Queen, [2013] HCA 37, 302 A.L.R. 192, at para. 43; R. v. Amos, [2012] NSWSC 1021, at paras. 43 and 82). A young person with cognitive impairments may struggle to foresee the consequences of their actions or fully appreciate the harm caused to others, underscoring their diminished capacity for moral judgment.

[156] A young offender’s history and background are also relevant, as they can significantly shape a young person’s behaviour and judgment, and by extension, their development (s. 72(1)(a); Chol, at para. 61; B.J.M., at para. 110). That said, a young offender’s background encapsulates many aspects. Social context evidence, which I will consider below, may be relevant. Moreover, certain experiences, such as exposure to traumatic events, may fundamentally change their worldview and therefore their vulnerability, maturity, and capacity for moral judgment.

[159] Finally, although I.M. initially argued that expert evidence would always be necessary to assist in a youth justice court’s determination of whether the presumption is rebutted, at the hearing, this point was properly conceded. In my view, expert evidence is not required to rebut the presumption, though it may provide valuable assistance in certain cases (see, e.g., R. v. B.J.M., 2022 SKPC 38 (“B.J.M. Prov. Ct.”), at para. 47). This reflects the balance struck by Parliament in s. 72(1) to grant flexibility to sentencing judges to determine the most appropriate tools for assessing a youth offender’s moral blameworthiness when considering the practical realities of sentencing.

[160] Section 34(2) YCJA authorizes youth justice courts to order an assessment by a qualified expert on an application for an adult sentence. Section 34(1) permits youth justice courts, in their discretion, to determine whether to order a youth offender to be assessed by a qualified person, provided that the court believes a psychological report is necessary for an enumerated purpose and the young person is alleged to have committed a “serious violent offence”. Section 34(3) provides courts with the authority to remand a youth offender into custody to facilitate the preparation of such an assessment. While these assessments are distinct from expert evidence that may be tendered by the Crown or defence, they serve as a useful resource for courts in evaluating a youth’s developmental maturity.

(c) Social Context Evidence Relevant to Rebutting the Presumption

[164] This Court has addressed in a number of cases the mandatory direction in s. 718.2(e) Cr. C. that sentencing judges consider the unique situation of Indigenous offenders (R. v. Gladue, [1999] 1 S.C.R. 688, at para. 93; R. v. Ipeelee, 2012 SCC 13, [2012] 1 S.C.R. 433, at paras. 84-85). However, it has also generally recognized that an offender’s background and personal circumstances are relevant to their individual moral responsibility (Hills, at para. 58), and that systemic factors will be important in sentencing non-Aboriginal offenders as well (Gladue, at para. 69; Ipeelee, at para. 77). While this Court has not yet specifically considered the role of social context evidence in the sentencing of non-Indigenous offenders, jurisprudence from provincial appellate courts indicates that it can provide helpful guidance to understand the particular experience of an offender and their moral culpability. This is especially true with respect to offenders who belong to racialized groups who face overt and systemic discrimination (see Morris; R. v. Anderson, 2021 NSCA 62, 405 C.C.C. (3d) 1; R. v. Ellis, 2022 BCCA 278, 417 C.C.C. (3d) 102, at para. 78; R. v. C.K., 2022 QCCA 539, at para. 22; R. v. Pierre, 2023 ABCA 300, at para. 6; see also Hills, at para. 55).

[165] ….I recall that the YCJA expressly directs that measures taken against young persons should respect “ethnic, cultural and linguistic differences and respond to the needs of aboriginal young persons” (s. 3(1)(c)(iv))….

[166] The social context in which a young offender grows up can often affect the trajectory of their life. Understanding that trajectory helps place the young offender’s decisions in context, potentially demonstrating increased vulnerability, diminished judgment, and a reduced capacity for moral decision making. As the court explained in Morris, “an offender’s life experiences can . . . influence the choices made by the offender, and can explain, to some degree at least, why an offender made a choice to commit a particular crime in the specified circumstances” (para. 75). For example, as the intervener Justice for Children and Youth submits, gang affiliation can for some young persons act as a “refuge-seeking response to social dislocation or a lack of family stability, physical protection, or emotional or financial support” (I.F., at para. 33)….

C. Assessing Whether a Youth Sentence Would Not Be of Sufficient Length To Hold the Young Person Accountable (Section 72(1)(b))

(1) The Onus on the Crown To Satisfy the Sentencing Judge That an Adult Sentence Is Required for Accountability Under Section 72(1)(b)

[169] ….Once the Crown meets its burden of rebutting the presumption in s. 72(1)(a), it must still demonstrate that a youth sentence would be insufficient in length to hold the young person accountable for their wrongful conduct under s. 72(1)(b) to obtain an order for an adult sentence. The exercise under s. 72(1)(b) relates to assessing the fitness of a youth sentence in the circumstances. As such, the burden on the Crown is to satisfy the sentencing judge in the exercise of their discretion that the youth sentence is not of sufficient length to hold the young person accountable. Unlike s. 72(1)(a), the burden on this prong is not beyond a reasonable doubt but one of satisfaction, suited to the kind of discretionary exercise sentencing judges typically undertake when weighing competing factors to determine a fit sentence.

[171] Accountability under the YCJA reflects an equilibrium between different purposes: [TRANSLATION] “Rather than adopting a strictly punitive approach, the YCJA favours accountability aimed at transforming the young offender through measures tailored to their development and their capacity for reintegration” (Destrempe Rochette, at p. 72). For example, the YCJA requires sentencing judges to consider, in measuring the proper sanction to be imposed, the harm caused to victims (ss. 3(1)(c)(ii) and 38(3)(b)), alongside rehabilitation and reintegration into society, which are all understood to “contribut[e] to the long-term protection of the public” (s. 38(1)). The rules in the YCJA are different from those that apply to adult offenders, recognizing, as one scholar noted, an understanding that “children cannot be viewed merely as chronologically younger than adults, but rather as inherently vulnerable and immature human beings whose behavioural development and character formation remains ongoing” (Jones, at p. 97).

[172] ….This is an inherently contextual task rooted in judicial discretion (paras. 46-50). Accordingly, an assessment of the appropriateness of a youth sentence does not lend itself to proof beyond a reasonable doubt (see B.J.M., at paras. 91-99).

(2) Factors Relevant to Accountability Under Section 72(1)(b)

[174] The assessment under s. 72(1)(b) is not merely procedural or perfunctory. It engages with fundamental principles of youth sentencing, particularly those outlined in ss. 3(1)(b)(ii) and 38. A young offender does not lose the statutory guardrail of s. 72(1)(b) simply because they are developmentally mature. The statutory context makes clear that the accountability inquiry is not a foregone conclusion once the presumption inscribed in s. 72(1)(a) is rebutted; it remains a distinct and essential assessment.

[175] ….The fact that a youth’s developmental age may be comparable to an adult does not, in itself, justify the imposition of an adult sentence.

[176] Similarly, s. 38(2)(c) links proportionality to the seriousness of the offence and the offender’s degree of responsibility, while also prioritizing rehabilitation and restraint over denunciation and deterrence. Notably, general deterrence is excluded as a sentencing objective for young persons (R. v. B.W.P., 2006 SCC 27, [2006] 1 S.C.R. 941, at para. 4). This is further reinforced by the YCJA’s provisions on custodial sentences. For example, s. 39(1) restricts such sentences to exceptional cases (C.D., at para. 39). Even for first degree murder, the maximum custodial sentence under the YCJA is six years (s. 42(2)(q)(i)). These principles inform the meaning of accountability under s. 72(1)(b).

[178] The breadth of the discretionary inquiry under the second prong necessarily includes examining relevant aspects of the offender’s background to better understand their choices leading to, and their individual responsibility for, the crime (Hills, at para. 58). Accordingly, sentencing judges must balance the aggravating and mitigating circumstances of the offence and the offender, including their post-offence conduct and pre-sentence behaviour, to determine if a youth sentence falls short of delivering meaningful accountability. The assessment thus parallels the determination of a fit sentence, which must balance the offence’s gravity with the offender’s culpability (L.M., at para. 17; Ruby, at §23.6; Vauclair, Desjardins and Lachance, at para. 47.2).

[179] As the Court of Appeal decided in the companion case of S.B., social context evidence is often indispensable in assessing a young person’s accountability (R. v. S.B., 2023 ONCA 369, 426 C.C.C. (3d) 367, at para. 71). I agree. Such information can shed light on the vulnerabilities arising from the offender’s background and therefore may assist in establishing a nuanced understanding of the offender’s conduct and culpability (see Morris, at paras. 13 and 97; see also Hills, at paras. 55 and 58). For example, evidence of socioeconomic disadvantage and exposure to violence may indicate that a harsher, adult‑style sentence is not appropriate, as it could exacerbate the young person’s vulnerabilities. Thus, social context evidence plays a dual role under s. 72(1). While it may be critical in the factual inquiry under the first prong, it is equally vital to understanding whether the available youth sentence would sufficiently hold the young offender accountable.[Emphasis by PJM]

[181] In sum, the accountability inquiry under s. 72(1)(b) must be understood as a distinct, normative decision that is predicated on — and only follows after — a rigorous factual inquiry into developmental age. It requires courts to balance the principles of proportionality, accountability, and rehabilitation in determining whether a youth sentence is adequate. This analysis reflects the YCJA’s overarching goals of promoting meaningful consequences, fostering reintegration, and addressing the harm caused by youth offences. By grounding the inquiry in these principles, judges can ensure that decisions are fair, individualized, and consistent with the needs of young offenders.

VIII. Application

B. Errors in Principle Justify Intervention by This Court

[187] First, the sentencing judge erred in law by applying the wrong standard of proof to the Crown’s burden under s. 72(1)(a). The presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness requires the Crown to establish, beyond a reasonable doubt, that the young person’s developmental age, at the time of the offence, was akin to that of an adult. Instead, the sentencing judge applied a lower threshold, requiring only “satisfaction after careful consideration by the court of all the relevant factors” (para. 25, quoting B.L., at para. 36). This failure to apply the correct standard constitutes an error in principle. By lowering the burden on the Crown, the sentencing judge distorted the required analysis, making it significantly easier to rebut the presumption than constitutionally required.

[190] Secondly, the sentencing judge in the present case erred by improperly considering the seriousness of the offence at the first prong. He considered this factor at the outset of his reasons. Although the sentencing judge recognized that this factor did not alone justify an adult sentence (at para. 29), it was in point of fact irrelevant to rebutting the presumption altogether. He then noted it again as a key factor in his ultimate conclusion that I.M. demonstrated the maturity, moral sophistication, and capacity for independent judgment of an adult (para. 38). Respectfully stated, this reasoning reflects a legal error. The objective seriousness of the offence does not speak to, and has no bearing upon, a young person’s developmental age.

C. Resentencing I.M. on Appeal

(1) The Crown Did Not Discharge its Burden To Rebut the Presumption Under Section 72(1)(a)

[199] At the time of the offence, I.M. was 17 years and 5 months old. It was not a mistake for the sentencing judge, or for the Court of Appeal, to observe that I.M. was on the “cusp” of his 18th birthday when he committed the offence (he was in fact about 7 months away from that date). But, at best, it was one contextual factor among others relevant to developmental age. I.M. was no less entitled, by statute and as a matter of constitutional law, to the benefit of the presumption of diminished moral culpability simply because he was close to coming of age. While proximity to adulthood may lean in favour of rebutting the presumption, it is not sufficient. Even those on the cusp of adulthood are presumed to have diminished moral blameworthiness in the absence of contrary evidence. On re-sentencing, the Court must begin from the premise that I.M.’s developmental age is coincident with his chronological age at the time of the offence. If the Crown is unable to prove otherwise beyond a reasonable doubt, then I.M. remains entitled to the benefit of the presumption and must be sentenced as a young person and held to account for the murder for which he was convicted under s. 42(2) YCJA.[Emphasis by PJM]

[200] I turn first to the sentencing judge’s findings of fact in respect of the violent circumstances of the murder of S.T. and I.M.’s role in the death. The sentencing judge fairly relied on such facts to assess the extent of I.M.’s involvement in the offence, as signs that I.M. planned the robbery in an adult-like manner. However, on closer inspection, some of these facts also raise questions about I.M.’s impulsiveness, susceptibility to peer influence, and propensity for risk-taking.

[201] First are the facts surrounding I.M.’s motivations for getting involved in the robbery that led to S.T.’s murder. The Crown points to evidence showing that I.M. wanted a firearm in the period leading up to and following the offence (R.F., at para. 8 and passim). It alludes to the text message I.M. sent to one of the adult co-conspirators that he — I.M. — saw the robbery as his “cum.up” to a more serious career in crime (para. 9). I accept, as the sentencing judge did, that these facts speak to I.M.’s involvement. At the same time, the “cum.up” framing is also consistent with adolescent risk-taking, susceptibility to influence of older criminal actors, and a young person’s failure to measure consequences as carefully as someone with the developmental age of an adult. These facts raise at least some reasonable doubt as to I.M.’s alleged developmental maturity. The Crown, in my view, gave no consideration to this matter and did not dispel the negative inferences it raises in rebutting the presumption.

[202] Second are the facts surrounding I.M.’s interactions with his schoolmate G.D. soon after the offence. The sentencing judge relied on G.D.’s testimony that I.M. described his involvement in S.T.’s death and showed him a bloodied shirt. The judge cited this as evidence “[i]mplicating I.M.” and as post-offence conduct that exacerbated the seriousness of the murder (heading of para. 11; see also para. 33). For I.M. to declare to a young peer four days after the event that he stabbed another youth, and to then display the victim’s bloodied clothes, was ill-considered and imprudent in the extreme. It showed bravado consonant with the impulsivity of an adolescent and stood in contrast to the capacity for moral judgment that one would expect from an adult. While these findings may establish I.M.’s role, they also stand as an obstacle that the Crown must overcome to rebut the presumption.

[205] On its face, I.M.’s difficult life circumstances are suggestive of a heightened vulnerability that reinforces, rather than overcomes, the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness (D.B., at para. 41). Situating I.M.’s early criminal involvement in this context supports the view that his behaviour is consistent with adolescents’ susceptibility to peer pressure, proneness to risk-taking, and tendency to not appreciate long term consequences. The Crown’s onus required it to explain how, notwithstanding these difficulties, I.M. had the moral sophistication and capacity for judgment beyond his years at the time of the offence.

[206] The record before this Court does not support this conclusion. The Crown’s mistaken insistence on a holistic approach to ss. 72(1)(a) and 72(1)(b) based on moral blameworthiness meant that it neglected to address how I.M.’s background affected his developmental age. The Crown did not address how evidence concerning I.M.’s background was relevant to his vulnerability or to his capacity for moral judgment. The Crown failed to discharge its burden on this point as well.

[207] I.M.’s mental health at the time of the offence presents yet another obstacle in the face of the Crown’s position. The most direct evidence in this regard comes from Dr. Pearce’s forensic psychiatric report. The sentencing judge relied on Dr. Pearce’s evidence to conclude that I.M.’s “adolescent-onset conduct disorder” and other mental health problems meant that his rehabilitative prognosis at that time was negative (para. 59). However, Dr. Pearce’s report also sheds light on I.M.’s developmental maturity. He observed that I.M. exhibited impulsivity and poor emotional regulation, both of which are characteristic of youth who have not yet developed full adult moral judgment. He found that I.M.’s peer delinquency, supervision failures, and low school achievement reflected social susceptibility, external instability, and limited cognitive development (A.R., vol. I, at pp. 120-22).

[208] In all, these findings undermine the Crown’s proposition that I.M. exhibited adult-level reasoning and judgment at the time of the offence, roughly eight years prior to Dr. Pearce’s examination. The Crown’s submissions with respect to Dr. Pearce’s assessment do not overcome the doubt that his report raises: in this Court, the Crown noted simply Dr. Pearce’s conclusion that it was unclear to him that I.M.’s ingrained maladaptive personality traits and adolescent-onset disorder affected his rehabilitative prognosis in 2019. Nothing is said by the Crown about the impact of I.M.’s mental health problems on his capacity for moral judgment at the time of the offence (R.F., at para. 110).

[211] In sum, there is some evidence on the record that supports the Crown’s argument that the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness has been rebutted. There remains, however, important unanswered evidence of impulsivity and conduct shaped by adult peer influence: I.M.’s “cum.up” comment, his boastful description to G.D., his decision to show the bloodied clothing, and Dr. Pearce’s report. These facts leave one with the impression that I.M. showed signs of youthful bravado, impulsivity and propensity to risk-taking. They also suggest that he was susceptible to peer influence and adult pressure. The reasonable doubt that arises with these facts presents an obstacle to the Crown’s argument that the presumption has been rebutted.

[212] Viewing the evidence in its totality on re-sentencing, I conclude the Crown has failed to discharge its onus to rebut the presumption of diminished moral blameworthiness. It was incumbent on the Crown to demonstrate, beyond a reasonable doubt, that I.M.’s developmental age was that of an adult, and dispel the evidence suggesting that I.M.’s developmental age — psychologically, socially, and morally — was in fact consonant with his chronological age. There is no question that sentenced as a young person I.M. will be held to account for his criminal conduct, but that is not the inquiry under s. 72(1)(a). In the absence of a demonstration by the Crown that displaces the presumption to the standard of beyond a reasonable doubt, I.M. remains entitled to be sentenced as young person.

IX. Disposition

[223] I would allow the appeal, set aside the adult sentence imposed by the sentencing judge, and sentence I.M. afresh by imposing on him a youth sentence of six years of committal to custody and four years of placement under conditional supervision pursuant to s. 42(2)(q)(i) YCJA, calculated from July 31, 2020, the date of the sentencing judge’s reasons…..

R v Stewart, 2025 NSCA 57

[July 24, 2025] Consent, Blackout and R v Villaroman [Reasons by Bourgeois J.A. with Bryson and Van den Eynden JJ.A. concurring] 

AUTHOR’S NOTE: Blackout intoxication and its implications for consent in sexual assault cases

When a sexual assault complainant is intoxicated to the point of blackout, it presents substantial evidentiary challenges for the Crown. There are two key problems:

  1. Inability to recall events:
    A complainant who experiences a blackout is unable to provide a full account of what occurred during the period of lost memory. This creates gaps in the narrative, undermines the completeness of the testimony, and limits the complainant’s ability to describe key interactions, including whether they consented or objected to the sexual activity.

  2. The effect of intoxication on conduct:
    At law, it is recognized that intoxication may cause individuals to act in ways they would not have chosen to while sober. As a result, a complainant’s sober belief about what they “would have” done—for example, that they never would have consented—is of limited probative value in assessing whether consent was given during the period of intoxication. This undermines retrospective assertions of non-consent that are based solely on character or predisposition.

Under the framework set out in R v Villaroman, which requires triers of fact to consider reasonable alternative inferences that arise from the evidence, this combination can be significant. Where there is no direct evidence of non-consent, and the complainant cannot recall the critical period due to intoxication, the defence may argue that a reasonable inference is that the complainant did, in fact, consent during that period—even if they later regretted or denied that consent.

This does not mean that blackout intoxication precludes conviction, but it does impose a higher evidentiary burden on the Crown. Courts must consider whether the accused’s guilt is the only reasonable inference available, given the evidence and the gaps in memory. When alternate inferences—like consent given in the moment—remain plausible and are supported by the evidence, an acquittal should follow.


Reasons for judgment:

[1] After a six day trial in the Provincial Court of Nova Scotia, the appellant, Dante Stewart, was convicted of sexual assault contrary to s. 271 of the Criminal Code. 1 He was subsequently sentenced to a 2 year term in a federal institution by the trial judge, Judge Kelly J. Serbu.

Background

[3] The trial was heard over several days during the fall of 2023. There was no dispute regarding the general events giving rise to the allegation of sexual assault. Specifically, the appellant and the complainant were known to each other and shared a common group of friends. Several members of that group met at the appellant’s home on the evening and early morning of February 9 and 10, 2021, including the complainant.

[4] Some consumed alcohol. Some consumed drugs. Some consumed both. As the evening continued, the complainant became quite intoxicated and friends put her to lay down in the appellant’s bed. Her friends later left. The complainant stayed. There is no dispute that at some point later, the appellant came to bed, and he and the complainant engaged in sexual activity. It is that activity that gave rise to the charge of sexual assault against the appellant.

[6] The Crown called the complainant as its first witness. Her testimony included:

• She had brought a quart of vodka with her, which she was drinking from the bottle, chased with orange juice. She drank about half the bottle;

• The group was downstairs in a small room the appellant used for recording music. She took a “bar” of Xanax and that was the last thing she “solidly remembered before blacking out”;

• When she “came to” she was crying and confused and feeling pain. She said “I was being penetrated anally and I was crying and telling him it hurt and to stop”. The appellant said nothing, and continued with the anal penetration, despite her cries to stop, until he ejaculated;

• She did not recall anything that happened in the appellant’s bedroom prior to coming out of her “blackout”;

• She stated she had not consented to “any sexual activity” with the appellant. She further said she did not consent to the anal sex.

[8] The appellant chose to testify. He asserted:

• Once he got in bed, the complainant immediately turned towards him and started kissing him. They began touching each other, and he began “fingering” her, but her underwear got in the way. The complainant removed her pants one leg at a time and then her underwear. They continued kissing and touching. In crossexamination, he denied removing the complainant’s clothes, repeating it was she who removed her own pants and underwear;

• After the sexual activity had continued for some time, the complainant got up and placed herself in the “doggie” position on the bed. The appellant stood on the floor by the bed and they engaged in vaginal sexual intercourse in that position. He said things progressed: “I put my penis in her vagina and we were having sex like that. Throughout that I started putting my thumb in her butt just playing around and I spit on it a little bit, right, just trying to lube it up, and then once I thought everything was good, I put it in her butt”;

• There was no conversation between he and the complainant at any time during the sexual encounter. She was not crying at any time, nor did she ask him to stop. If he thought she didn’t want to engage, he “would have backed off . . . instantly”;

• He believed the complainant was consenting to what was happening as she had “110 percent come on” to him.

[19] The trial judge then commenced his analysis. The first issue he addressed was whether the complainant, as alleged by the Crown, lacked the capacity to consent. He firmly rejected that argument:

Focusing on this case, the evidence before this Court is that approximately ten minutes before the accused, Mr. Stewart, got into his bed with the complainant while he was fully clothed, the complainant had a conversation with her friend, [R.], for a few minutes, and she was asked by her friend to go home with her. The evidence is clear that the complainant . . . was adamant about staying in the bed and not wanting to leave with her friend. The evidence was not that the complainant was passed out and had no ability to communicate with her friend, [R.].

It appears from the evidence that the complainant . . . had the ability to communicate with her friend, [R.], and she made her decision to stay in the bed and not leave.

The Court heard evidence that the complainant . . . drank half a quart of vodka, took a piece of her Xanax bar, and possibly consumed powdered cocaine that evening. The Court heard no forensic or expert evidence relating to the possible impact of alcohol, or drugs, or the combination of them, could have had on the complainant . . . and her memory or capacity.

There is no evidence that the complainant . . . was passed out or incapacitated. The evidence was that she was saying things her friends thought were embarrassing to her, but no examples were provided to the Court, and [the complainant], the Court was told, was also annoying her group of friends by this conduct.

Based on the evidence before me, I am satisfied the complainant . . . had the capacity to consent.

(Emphasis added)

[20] The above finding, consistent with the appellant’s position at trial, and contrary to the Crown’s theory of culpability, has not been challenged on appeal….

[21] The trial judge then turned to the question of whether the complainant had consented to the sexual activity with the appellant. It is useful to recall the Crown’s position was the complainant had not consented to any of the sexual activity. She had testified to the same effect. The trial judge’s analysis followed a path that neither party had argued at trial, nor were informed he was considering.6 As opposed to treating the sexual conduct globally, the trial judge divided the anal sexual activity from the rest, and assessed the appellant’s culpability separately for each.

[22] Beyond simply having a doubt, and despite the complainant’s assertion to the contrary, the trial judge expressly found the complainant had, in fact, consented to the initial sexual activity:

The evidence on the initial sexual activity only comes from the accused, Mr. Stewart. It is uncontradicted.7 I have no reason not to accept the evidence of Mr. Stewart as to what initially took place in bed with the complainant prior to the anal sexual activity.

I accept Mr. Stewart’s evidence as it relates to what initially took place in the bed, prior to the anal sexual activity. Based on Mr. Stewart’s evidence, I find that the complainant . . . consented to the initial sexual conduct described by

Mr. Stewart when he initially got into his bed with the complainant, prior to the anal sexual activity.

Applying the W.(D.) framework to the initial sexual activity, and again prior to the anal sexual activity, I find that the complainant consented to the sexual activity. The Crown has not satisfied the Court that the sexual activity that took place prior to the anal sexual activity constitutes a sexual assault.

(Emphasis added)

[23] The above conclusion, again consistent with the appellant’s submission at trial, and contrary to the Crown’s theory of culpability, has not been challenged on appeal.

[24] The trial judge then moved on to consider whether the complainant had consented to the “anal sexual activity”. The entirety of his analysis in that regard is as follows:
….I reviewed the testimony multiple times and contrasted the evidence of the Crown against the Defence evidence, and I’ve applied the W.(D.) standard to that piece of evidence. The complainant . . . and the accused, Mr. Stewart, were both good witnesses. I am unable to prefer or accept one version of events over the other. I am not satisfied the Crown has proven beyond a reasonable doubt that the complainant told the accused to stop, or was crying during the anal sexual activity.

I am satisfied, however, that the complainant . . . in her own mind was not and did not consent to the anal sexual activity. The accused, Mr. Stewart, was clear in his evidence that he had no conversations with the complainant . . . at any time during any of the sexual activity with the complainant. In particular, he did not have any conversations or communication with the complainant relating to anal sexual activity.

(Emphasis added)

[25] The trial judge then turned to an assessment of whether the appellant had “an honest but mistaken belief that the complainant was consenting to the anal sexual activity” based on the evidence before him. He concluded the appellant did not, in the circumstances, establish such a belief.

[26] The trial judge reasoned:

Consent must be present at the time of the anal sexual activity. Did the accused, Mr. Stewart, honestly believe the complainant was effectively saying yes through her words, acts, that she was consenting to the anal sexual activity?

….The complainant’s lack of communication by remaining silent when the accused, Mr. Stewart, inserted his thumb in her anus, does not constitute consent, nor does it provide the accused, Mr. Stewart, with the basis to honestly believe that the complainant, having said yes to putting his thumb in her anus, that must’ve meant that he was okay and permitted to then put his penis in her anus….

I am not satisfied, based on the evidence before me, that the complainant had affirmatively communicated, by words or conduct, her agreement to engage in any anal sexual activity with the accused, Mr. Stewart. I find the accused, Mr. Stewart, took no steps to determine whether the complainant . . . would and was consenting to him inserting his thumb in her anus or his penis thereafter.

….I find the Crown has proven beyond a reasonable doubt that the accused committed a sexual assault on the complainant as it relates to all of the anal sexual activity.

[33] Before this Court, the appellant submits that given his other conclusions, the trial judge was precluded from finding beyond a reasonable doubt the complainant did not consent to “all of the anal sexual activity”. He argues there was only circumstantial evidence on the issue of her subjective consent for much of the encounter, and there were other reasonable findings available, notably the complainant did consent to all of the sexual activity. As such, it was unreasonable for the trial judge to conclude the Crown had proven the actus reus beyond a reasonable doubt.

[40] In assessing whether a verdict is unreasonable, or otherwise demonstrates an error of law, this Court must look to the decision the trial judge actually made, not one that could have been made. “It should also be borne in mind that the question whether a verdict is unreasonable is not the same as the question whether a different verdict would have been reasonable had the evidence presented at trial been interpreted differently.”9

[41] Given the arguments made, the first challenge in assessing whether the verdict was unreasonable is to ascertain what the trial judge decided. The appellant’s argument rests upon the trial judge having found the complainant did not consent to any of the anal sexual activity, much of which she did not remember, thus necessitating an application of the Villaroman principles relating to circumstantial evidence. As noted above, the Crown says those principles do not come into play because the trial judge, based on the complainant’s direct evidence, found she did not consent to the anal penetration.[Emphasis by PJM]

[44] With respect, I cannot accept the trial judge’s finding of subjective nonconsent was directed to the anal penetration the complainant recalled. Several times within the course of his reasons, the trial judge utilized the broader term “anal sexual activity” while clearly referencing aspects thereof that occurred during the complainant’s period of “blackout”. Based on the appellant’s evidence (which the trial judge had found credible and accepted) this would have included the progressive insertion of his thumb in her anus, applying spit to the area, and the anal penetration up to the time when the complainant “came to”. The trial judge’s conclusion is clear: “I find the Crown has proven beyond a reasonable doubt that the accused committed a sexual assault on the complainant as it relates to all of the anal sexual activity.”

[45] I acknowledge there was evidence offered by the complainant, which may have grounded a finding she did not consent to the anal penetration she remembered. But the trial judge did not make that finding, nor was that the basis of his conclusion the subjective non-consent aspect of the actus reus element had been proven beyond a reasonable doubt. Rather, the trial judge’s analysis of whether the complainant had subjectively consented to the “anal sexual activity” was focused on what had occurred during the time frame she did not remember. That evidence was entirely circumstantial and, as such, the principles in Villaroman ought to have been in play.[Emphasis by PJM]

[46] In Villaroman, Justice Cromwell provided the following direction:

[37] When assessing circumstantial evidence, the trier of fact should consider “other plausible theor[ies]” and “other reasonable possibilities” which are inconsistent with guilt: R. v. Comba, [1938] O.R. 200 (C.A.), at pp. 205 and 211, per Middleton J.A., aff’d [1938] S.C.R. 396; R. v. Baigent, 2013 BCCA 28, 335 B.C.A.C. 11, at para. 20; R. v. Mitchell, [2008] QCA 394 (AustLII), at para. 35. I agree with the appellant that the Crown thus may need to negative these reasonable possibilities, but certainly does not need to “negative every possible conjecture, no matter how irrational or fanciful, which might be consistent with the innocence of the accused”: R. v. Bagshaw, [1972] S.C.R. 2, at p. 8. “Other plausible theories” or “other reasonable possibilities” must be based on logic and experience applied to the evidence or the absence of evidence, not on speculation.

[38] Of course, the line between a “plausible theory” and “speculation” is not always easy to draw. But the basic question is whether the circumstantial evidence, viewed logically and in light of human experience, is reasonably capable of supporting an inference other than that the accused is guilty.

(Emphasis added)

[47] I am satisfied the verdict rendered was unreasonable. As described above, the finding of subjective non-consent was based primarily on circumstantial evidence. The trial judge was obligated to consider “other reasonable possibilities inconsistent with guilt”. The obvious possibility is that the complainant did consent to the anal sexual activity when it was happening, but she has no memory of doing so.[Emphasis by PJM]

[48] Although an appeal of deficient jury instructions on the use of circumstantial evidence, in R. v. Green, 2024 ABCA 118, the Alberta Court of Appeal provided useful guidance where a complainant lacks memory:

[22] The jury instructions on consent also referred to circumstantial evidence that might help the jury determine whether the complainant did not consent to the sexual activity. However, at no point was the jury instructed, specifically in relation to consent, that even if they accepted the complainant’s evidence of blackout and rejected the direct evidence of the appellants, they would have to find that all the circumstantial evidence which they accepted reasonably permitted only one inference, being that the complainant did not consent to the sexual activity with the appellants.

[23] On a functional review of the jury instructions in the context of the case as a whole, they did not make it clear to the jury that if the jury accepted the complainant’s evidence of blackout, that meant she had no memory of what occurred during the blackout. The resulting absence of evidence in and of itself does not equate to lack of consent or lack of capacity to consent. The jury was not instructed that they must exclude all reasonable possibilities other than lack of consent, including the possibility that the complainant consented (and communicated consent) to the sexual activity while in a state of blackout.

[24] These points were important in the context of this case considered as whole. The Crown’s argument focused on blackout as evidence of lack of capacity to consent, which increased the risk that the jury would not be alive to the potential for consent during blackout and the need to exclude that possibility before convicting.

[49] Further, in R. v. Demong, 2023 SKCA 109, a judge-alone conviction for sexual assault was set aside on appeal. There, the complainant had “scant” memory of the interaction giving rise to a sexual assault charge due to being intoxicated by alcohol and drugs. She could not remember most of the sexual intercourse that the appellant described as being consensual. She had testified she would not have consented to having sex with the appellant given he was her mother’s boyfriend and otherwise “gross”.

[50] In allowing the appeal from conviction, the Saskatchewan Court of Appeal found the trial judge erred in assessing whether subjective non-consent had been proven. Notably, the trial judge did not consider whether the complainant may have consented, when she normally would not have, due to being intoxicated:

[24] Courts have repeatedly recognized that intoxication can lead people to do things and make choices they would not have made if they were sober. . . .

[26] As a consequence, there was another inference that should have been considered by the trial judge. Even if the complainant would not have consented to having sex with Mr. Demong if she had been sober or, for that matter, had been less impaired, she may have consented because she was intoxicated. The trial judge not only failed to grapple with this possibility as required by Villaroman but came perilously close to expressly reversing the burden of proof on this point,….

[51] In my view, the trial judge here fell into the same error. The complainant was highly intoxicated and initiated sexual activity with the appellant. The trial judge expressly found she had subjectively consented to certain sexual activities during the period she could not remember. Unlike what is commonly done in such cases, the complainant was not asked about whether she would have consented to engaging sexually with the appellant more broadly, nor specifically about her proclivities regarding anal sexual activity. There was a reasonable possibility the complainant had consented.

[52] There was simply no evidence upon which the trial judge could have found the reasonable possibility – that the complainant had consented to the appellant placing his thumb in her anus, applying spit to it, or proceeding to penile anal penetration – had been negated. I hasten to add, that even if he had exclusively found the complainant did not consent to the anal sex during the time frame she remembered (which he did not), it would have been erroneous for the trial judge to use that finding alone to establish a lack of subjective consent to the previous anal sexual activity. The verdict was unreasonable on the first basis as outlined in C.P.

[53] I am also satisfied the trial judge’s reasons further demonstrate an unreasonable verdict on the second basis. With respect, the trial judge’s differing conclusions regarding the existence of subjective consent to the non-anal sexual activity and the lack of subjective consent to “all of the anal sexual activity” is illogical based on the evidence he accepted.

[56] It is difficult to ascertain how the trial judge reached differing conclusions on the issue of subjective consent. He appears to rely on the fact there was no verbal discussion regarding the anal activity to ground his finding of non-consent. Yet the same lack of discussion did not preclude the trial judge finding the complainant consented to the earlier sexual activity. On this same record, these different conclusions are illogical

[57] I agree with the appellant that it appears the trial judge may have, without any evidentiary basis, assumed the complainant would not have consented to the array of anal sexual activity. This would constitute an error of law.

[65] After careful consideration, I am satisfied the exercise of residual discretion to enter an acquittal is warranted in the particular circumstances before the Court….

Disposition

[71] For the reasons above, I would allow the appeal and enter an acquittal.

R v Rashed, 2025 ONCA 515

[July 16, 2025] Wilful Blindness and Accessory After the Fact [Reasons by Copeland J.A. with K. van Rensburg and Grant Huscroft JJ.A. concurring]

AUTHOR’S NOTE: Wilful Blindness and Accessory After the Fact: A Narrow Path to Liability

This case presents a particularly nuanced intersection between state of mind and party liability in criminal law. The prosecution relied on a theory of wilful blindness to establish that the accused was an accessory after the fact to a known offence—a legal pathway that is technically available but practically challenging to prove.

Key Legal Principles:

  1. Wilful Blindness
    Wilful blindness refers to a deliberate failure to inquire into facts that an accused suspects may be true, precisely because they do not want to confirm those suspicions. It is a mental state of purposeful ignorance, not mere negligence or recklessness, and requires actual subjective suspicion followed by a conscious choice not to seek clarification. It is not passive; it involves the suppression of inquiry.

  2. Accessory After the Fact
    To be convicted as an accessory after the fact, the accused must take intentional actions to assist someone who they know has committed an offence, for the purpose of helping them evade detection, arrest, or punishment. Knowledge of the underlying offence is essential; recklessness is not sufficient.

  3. Application of Wilful Blindness to Accessory Liability
    While wilful blindness can, in principle, satisfy the knowledge requirement for accessory after the fact, the bar remains high. The Crown must prove beyond a reasonable doubt that the accused subjectively suspected the offence had occurred and deliberately turned a blind eye to avoid confirming it.

    This presents a thread-the-needle problem for prosecutors:

    • If there is no direct evidence of actual knowledge or of deliberate suppression of suspicion,

    • And if the accused’s conduct could reasonably be explained by negligence, recklessness, or mere indifference,
      then the trier of fact must acquit under R v Villaroman, which requires considering all reasonable inferences consistent with innocence.

Practical Implication:

In the absence of specific evidence of the accused’s state of mind, relying on wilful blindness in an accessory after the fact prosecution is a precarious strategy. The distinction between recklessness (which is insufficient) and wilful blindness(which may be sufficient) is subtle, but crucial. Without clear proof that the accused chose not to know what they already strongly suspected, the Crown risks failing to meet the standard of proof required.


Copeland J.A.:

[1] This is a Crown appeal from a directed verdict of acquittal on a charge of accessory after the fact to murder.

[2] Ryan Kabuya-Ntumba was shot four or five times by Moadd Maadani in the Byward Market at approximately 3:13 a.m. on July 1, 2019. He died hours later in hospital, at approximately 5:46 a.m. The shooting and some of the events that preceded it were captured on video.

[3] Immediately after the shooting, the respondent helped Mr. Maadani, who had also been shot in the encounter with Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba, flee from Ottawa to Montreal. They attended a hospital in Montreal for treatment of Mr. Maadani’s gunshot wound. Because the injury was a gunshot wound, hospital staff contacted police. The respondent lied to Montreal police about how Mr. Maadani was shot. The evidence at trial showed that the acts by the respondent assisting Mr. Maadani to flee started immediately after the shooting, but before Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba died, and continued after the time Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba died until approximately 11:50 a.m. on July 1.

[4] The respondent was charged with being an accessory after the fact to murder, contrary to s. 240 of the Criminal Code, R.S.C. 1985, c. C-46, and being an accessory after the fact to possession of a loaded, restricted firearm without authorization, contrary to s. 463 of the Criminal Code. The respondent was jointly tried with Mr. Maadani, who was charged with second-degree murder and possession of a loaded, restricted firearm.

[5] Before the final instructions to the jury, the trial judge granted the respondent’s motion for a directed verdict of acquittal on the count of being an accessory after the fact to murder. The jury ultimately found the respondent guilty of being an accessory after the fact to possession of a loaded, restricted firearm. Mr. Maadani, who had asserted defences of self-defence and provocation, was convicted of second-degree murder and the firearm offence. 1

[6] The Crown appeals….

[8] I would dismiss the appeal. The trial judge did not err in declining to leave the offence of being an accessory after the fact to murder to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness. Wilful blindness can substitute for actual knowledge where the accused subjectively strongly suspects a fact (here, the death of Mr. KabuyaNtumba) and deliberately chooses not to inquire in order to avoid confirmation of that fact. In light of the narrow scope of the doctrine of wilful blindness, on the evidence in this trial, it was not open to a reasonable jury, properly instructed, to find that in the time after Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba died (after 5:46 a.m.) when the respondent continued to aid Mr. Maadani after the shooting – through their continued flight to Montreal and false statements to the police – he was wilfully blind to whether the victim had died. The evidence permitted an inference that the respondent knew that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was injured by Mr. Maadani’s gunfire, but not that the respondent knew anything about the nature of the injuries or that there was a probability they would be fatal. In other words, on the evidence at trial, a reasonable jury, properly instructed, could not find that the respondent suspected that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was dead and deliberately chose not to inquire to avoid being fixed with knowledge of his death.

[9] Further, on the evidence at trial, there was no air of reality to the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder. The victim died. There was no dispute that the acts of Mr. Maadani caused the victim’s death….

(3) Did the trial judge err in declining to leave the offence of being an accessory after the fact to murder to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness?

(i) Accessory after the fact to murder

[28] In the appeal of R. v. Osman, 2025 ONCA 516, heard together with this appeal and released concurrently, I review the law in relation to accessory after the fact offences in general and accessory after the fact to murder in particular. I do not repeat that analysis here, but focus on the aspects of it that are relevant to the wilful blindness issue in this appeal.

[29] Accessory after the fact offences require that the accessory accused have knowledge of the specific offence they are alleged to have assisted the principal to flee at the time they assist the principal. Knowledge that the principal has committed some criminal offence is insufficient: R. v. Duong (1998), 124 C.C.C. (3d) 392 (Ont. C.A.), at pp. 399-401, 403.

[30] The parties agree that the knowledge requirement for accessory offences can be satisfied by actual knowledge or wilful blindness: Duong, at pp. 401-02. [31] The parties agree that as an element of the offence of being an accessory after the fact to murder, the Crown must prove that the accessory’s acts that are alleged to have assisted the principal were committed after the victim is dead: Commentaries on the Laws of England in Four Books by Sir William Blackstone, 1898, Book Four, p. 1454; R. v. Knott, 2006 CanLII 6588 (Ont. S.C.), at p. 9; R. v. B.(A.), 1999 CanLII 6762 (B.C.S.C.), at paras. 19-22.

[32] For an accessory accused to be guilty of being an accessory after the fact to murder, the knowledge requirement of the offence requires that at the time the accessory assisted the principal to flee, the accessory knew or was wilfully blind to the fact that the principal had committed the specified offence – murder. For the accessory accused to have the required knowledge, they must, at the time they assist the principal to flee, know that the victim is dead or be wilfully blind to that fact

[33] The Crown conceded in this court and below that the count of being an accessory after the fact to murder could not be left to the jury on the basis that the respondent had actual knowledge of Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s death at the time he assisted Mr. Maadani to flee and lied to the Montreal police about the source of Mr. Maadani’s injuries in furtherance of that goal. Before 5:46 a.m., Mr. KabuyaNtumba was not dead, so the respondent could not have known of his death in that time period. And there was no evidence from which a reasonable jury, properly instructed, could find that the respondent learned (had actual knowledge) that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was dead while he was still assisting Mr. Maadani to flee.

[34] The issue in dispute on the first ground of appeal is whether the count of being an accessory after the fact to murder should have been left to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness. Specifically, was it open on the trial evidence for a reasonable jury, properly instructed, to find that in the time that the respondent continued to assist Mr. Maadani to flee after Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was, in fact, dead (after 5:46 a.m. on July 1), the respondent was wilfully blind to the fact that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had died?

(ii) Wilful blindness as a substitute for actual knowledge

[36] Justice Charron, writing for the court, explained the function and elements of wilful blindness in R. v. Briscoe, 2010 SCC 13, [2010] 1 S.C.R. 411, at para. 21:

Wilful blindness does not define the mens rea required for particular offences. Rather, it can substitute for actual knowledge whenever knowledge is a component of the mens rea. The doctrine of wilful blindness imputes knowledge to an accused whose suspicion is aroused to the point where he or she sees the need for further inquiries, but deliberately chooses not to make those inquiries. See Sansregret v. The Queen, 1985 CanLII 79 (SCC), [1985] 1 S.C.R. 570, and R. v. Jorgensen, 1995 CanLII 85 (SCC), [1995] 4 S.C.R. 55. As Sopinka J. succinctly put it in Jorgensen (at para. 103), “[a] finding of wilful blindness involves an affirmative answer to the question: Did the accused shut his eyes because he knew or strongly suspected that looking would fix him with knowledge?” [Emphasis in original.]

[37] In the words of Glanville Williams, “[a] court can properly find wilful blindness only where it can almost be said that the defendant actually knew” (emphasis added): as cited in Briscoe, at para. 23. See also R. v. Morrison, 2019 SCC 15, [2019] 2 S.C.R. 3, at paras. 97-99; R. v. Sandhu (1989), 50 C.C.C. (3d) 492 (Ont. C.A.), at p. 497.

[38] The jurisprudence on wilful blindness emphasizes that it is distinct from recklessness, as well as the importance of maintaining the distinction. Charron J. addresses this issue in Briscoe, at paras. 22-24:

Courts and commentators have consistently emphasized that wilful blindness is distinct from recklessness. The emphasis bears repeating. As the Court explained in Sansregret (at p. 584):

. . . while recklessness involves knowledge of a danger or risk and persistence in a course of conduct which creates a risk that the prohibited result will occur, wilful blindness arises where a person who has become aware of the need for some inquiry declines to make the inquiry because he does not wish to know the truth. He would prefer to remain ignorant. The culpability in recklessness is justified by consciousness of the risk and by proceeding in the face of it, while in wilful blindness it is justified by the accused’s fault in deliberately failing to inquire when he knows there is reason for inquiry. [Emphasis added.]

It is important to keep the concepts of recklessness and wilful blindness separate. Glanville Williams explains the key restriction on the doctrine:

The rule that wilful blindness is equivalent to knowledge is essential, and is found throughout the criminal law. It is, at the same time, an unstable rule, because judges are apt to forget its very limited scope. A court can properly find wilful blindness only where it can almost be said that the defendant actually knew. He suspected the fact; he realised its probability; but he refrained from obtaining the final confirmation because he wanted in the event to be able to deny knowledge. This, and this alone, is wilful blindness. It requires in effect a finding that the defendant intended to cheat the administration of justice. Any wider definition would make the doctrine of wilful blindness indistinguishable from the civil doctrine of negligence in not obtaining knowledge. [Emphasis added.]

(Criminal Law: The General Part (2nd ed. 1961), at p. 159 (cited in Sansregret, at p. 586).)

Professor Don Stuart makes the useful observation that the expression “deliberate ignorance” seems more descriptive than “wilful blindness”, as it connotes “an actual process of suppressing a suspicion”. Properly understood in this way, “the concept of wilful blindness is of narrow scope and involves no departure from the subjective focus on the workings of the accused’s mind” (Canadian Criminal Law: A Treatise (5th ed. 2007), at p. 241). While a failure to inquire may be evidence of recklessness or criminal negligence, as for example, where a failure to inquire is a marked departure from the conduct expected of a reasonable person, wilful blindness is not simply a failure to inquire but, to repeat Professor Stuart’s words, “deliberate ignorance”. [All emphasis from Briscoe.]

See also Morrison, at para. 100.

[39] The distinction between wilful blindness and recklessness is important in this appeal because the Crown does not argue that the trial judge should have left accessory after the fact to murder to the jury on the basis that the respondent was reckless as to whether Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was dead at the time the respondent assisted Mr. Maadani to flee. At the outset of oral argument, the Crown abandoned the submission that recklessness in relation to knowledge of death is sufficient mens rea for accessory after the fact to murder.3

[40] I would emphasize the language used in formulating the wilful blindness standard from Glanville Williams and Jorgensen (quoted above in Briscoe) that for wilful blindness to be present, more is required than that the accused knows there is a risk of some consequence. Proceeding in the face of knowledge of risk establishes recklessness, but not wilful blindness. Wilful blindness requires that the accused subjectively knows or strongly suspects that the consequence has happened (or will happen depending on the circumstances) and deliberately chooses not to inquire further because the accused subjectively knows or strongly suspects that inquiring will fix them with knowledge. This speaks to the accused’s belief that there is a level of probability of the consequence at issue, not just a risk. The accused must have “suspected the fact; realized its probability; but he refrained from obtaining final confirmation because he wanted to be able to deny knowledge” (Glanville Williams, Criminal Law: The General Part, 2nd ed., (London: Stevens & Sons Ltd., 1961), at p. 159). The accused must have “shut his eyes because he knew or strongly suspected that looking would fix him with knowledge” (Jorgensen, at para. 103). This notion of probability of the consequence and that the accused is deliberately shutting their eyes to it are what separate wilful blindness from recklessness.

[41] In the context of this appeal, for the count of being an accessory after the fact to murder to have been left to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness, the evidence would need to allow a reasonable jury, properly instructed, to conclude that the respondent realized it was probable that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had died at some point during the night, and deliberately chose to remain ignorant. In other words, that the respondent knew it was probable that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had died during the night, and refrained from inquiring because he wanted to be able to deny knowledge of that fact. Indeed, in oral submissions, Crown counsel framed the inference that she argued was available on the trial evidence this way: at the time the respondent assisted Mr. Maadani to flee, the respondent knew that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had “been fatally shot” and was “dead or dying”.

[42] If the evidence only allowed an inference that the respondent knew that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was injured by gunfire but nothing about the nature of the injuries, and continued to assist Mr. Maadani to escape while being indifferent to the nature of Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s injuries and their potential consequences, that would not be sufficient to leave the count of being an accessory after the fact to murder to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness.

(iii) The trial judge did not err in declining to leave to the jury the offence of being an accessory after the fact to murder on the basis of wilful blindness

[46] Reviewing the issue on a correctness standard, I am not persuaded that the evidence at trial would allow a reasonable jury, properly instructed, to find that, during the time the respondent assisted Mr. Maadani to flee, he was wilfully blind to Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s death. It follows that the trial judge did not err in declining to leave the offence of being an accessory after the fact to murder to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness. Having reached this conclusion, it is not necessary to consider the Crown’s arguments of specific errors in the trial judge’s reasoning.

[47] In order for accessory after the fact to murder to be left to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness, the evidence bearing on the respondent’s knowledge of Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s death would need to allow a reasonable jury, properly instructed, to conclude that the respondent realized there was a probability that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had died at some point during the night, and deliberately chose to remain ignorant to avoid being fixed with knowledge that he was dead. If the evidence only allowed an inference that the respondent knew that Mr. KabuyaNtumba had been injured by gunfire, but not the nature of the injuries, and continued to assist Mr. Maadani to escape while being indifferent to the nature of Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s injuries and their potential consequences, that would not be sufficient to leave accessory after the fact to murder to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness.

[48] The evidence did not provide a basis for a reasonable jury, properly instructed, to find that the respondent was aware there was a probability that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had died during the night, and deliberately chose not to inquire to avoid being fixed with that knowledge.

[50] The primary point on which I disagree with the Crown’s position is that I am not persuaded the evidence permitted the inference that at the time the respondent fled the scene of the shooting, he knew that there was a probability that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was fatally injured and dying. The evidence at trial only went so far as to support the inference that the respondent knew that Mr. KabuyaNtumba had been injured by gunfire, but not that he knew the nature of the injuries or that it was probable they would be fatal. In that context, while it is true that there was no evidence that the respondent made any inquiries during the flight to Montreal about whether Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had died, in the absence of a basis for the inference that the respondent knew it was probable that Mr. KabuyaNtumba was fatally injured, it is not reasonable to infer a deliberate choice by the respondent not to inquire in order to avoid being fixed with knowledge of death.

[51] I turn then to the evidence and what reasonable inferences it supported in relation to the respondent’s knowledge about Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s death.

[52] In the altercation immediately prior to the shooting, the video exhibits show Mr. Maadani reaching several times into the satchel he was wearing, and the respondent placing his hand over the satchel. It was open to the jury to infer from this evidence, in the context of all of the evidence, that the respondent was aware Mr. Maadani was armed.

[53] The forensic evidence of bullet casings found at the scene supported that five bullets were fired from Mr. Maadani’s gun and one from Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s gun. The video exhibits show the respondent standing beside Mr. Maadani at the time the shooting began. Although the video has no sound, four muzzle flashes are visible from Mr. Maadani’s gun and one from Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s gun. The jury could reasonably infer that the respondent was aware of the shots being fired by Mr. Maadani towards Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba, at least from hearing them.

[54] In addition, I conclude the jury could reasonably infer that the respondent was aware that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had been hit by at least one bullet. On the video Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba can be seen falling to the ground in the same time frame as the muzzle flashes from Mr. Maadani’s gun.

[55] Based on the video evidence in the context of the evidence as a whole, I conclude that it was open on the evidence for the jury to find that in addition to hearing the shots fired by Mr. Maadani, the respondent was facing Mr. KabuyaNtumba when the first shot was fired.

[56] However, the video shows the respondent turn and run almost immediately when the shooting happens. Thus, while the jury could reasonably find that the respondent knew that Mr. Maadani had fired multiple shots toward Mr. KabuyaNtumba and that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba had been hit by at least one bullet, the evidence could not support a finding that the respondent knew the specifics of Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s injuries or that it was probable they would be fatal.

[57] I pause to observe that there is no question that gunshot injuries constitute serious bodily harm. But the practical reality is that not all gunshot wounds are fatal. For the Crown to rely on wilful blindness in relation to the death of the victim, the Crown must show that the accused has some level of knowledge of the probability of death of the victim, as opposed to the possibility.

[58] Beyond the evidence of what the respondent himself could have observed and known about the injuries to Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba, the evidence of other witnesses did not support the conclusion that at the time the respondent fled the scene and soon after, it was apparent that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s injuries were likely to be fatal.

[59] On the video, after the muzzle flashes and after Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba fell to the ground, he got to his feet and ran southbound down Dalhousie Street and then collapsed (in the video he was behind a vehicle at this point, so not visible to the camera once he was on the ground).

[63] The fact of Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba getting to his feet and running after he fell to the ground, as well as the evidence of the observations of the civilians and their perspective on Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s injuries, undermine the inference sought by the Crown that a reasonable jury could infer that it was apparent at the time the shots were fired and soon after – to observers, in general, and to the respondent, in particular – that Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba’s injuries were likely to be fatal.

[69] My point is not that statements from the accused bearing on wilful blindness – direct evidence – are always required in order to leave wilful blindness to a jury as a substitute for actual knowledge. Depending on the full evidentiary picture, circumstantial evidence can provide a basis to leave wilful blindness to a jury. But given the limits of the circumstantial evidence bearing on wilful blindness in this case, the comparison to the evidence in Duong and Briscoe is helpful in maintaining the vital distinction between recklessness and wilful blindness. In this case, there is no evidence similar to that in Duong or Briscoe to fill the evidentiary gap in relation to whether the respondent made a deliberate choice not to inquire as to whether Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba was dead.

[73] This court has not ruled on whether recklessness as to the offence committed by the principal can satisfy the mens rea for accessory after the fact offences: see Duong, at p. 401. Because the Crown abandoned the argument that recklessness can satisfy the mens rea, I would not rule on the issue in this appeal. But I would observe that the language defining the mens rea in s. 23 of the Criminal Code as “knowing that a person [i.e., the principal] has been a party to the offence, receives, comforts or assists that person for the purpose of enabling that person to escape” (emphasis added) would appear to make the argument that recklessness can satisfy the mens rea a difficult one: R. v. Zora, 2020 SCC 14, [2020] 2 S.C.R. 3, at para. 117; Sandhu, at pp. 497-98.

[74] To allow the charge of accessory after the fact to murder in this case to go to the jury on the basis of wilful blindness would undermine the important distinction between wilful blindness and recklessness.

(4) There was no air of reality to the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder

[78] In the companion appeal of Osman, the court holds that the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder can be an included offence to being an accessory after the fact to murder. However, where the victim dies, it will be rare that there is an air of reality to the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder as an included offence to being an accessory after the fact to murder, and thus, rare that a trial judge will be required to instruct a jury on the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder. Without foreclosing the categories in which there could be an air of reality to the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder as an included offence in cases where the victim dies, the only circumstance that appears realistic on the cases relied on by the Crown is where there is a live issue as to whether the culpable act of the principal caused the death of the victim. I do not reproduce the analysis from Osman, but adopt and apply it in this appeal.

[79] In this case, as in Osman, whether there was an air of reality to accessory after the fact to attempted murder turns on the fact that there was no live issue at trial that the acts of the principal, Mr. Maadani, caused the death of the victim, Mr. Kabuya-Ntumba.

[80] In this case, there was no air of reality to the conclusion that Mr. Maadani committed attempted murder, and as a result, no air of reality to the conclusion that the respondent committed the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder.

[85] For these reasons, the trial judge did not err in not leaving to the jury, as an included offence, the offence of being an accessory after the fact to attempted murder.

Disposition

[87] The trial judge did not err in directing a verdict of acquittal on the count of being an accessory after the fact to murder. I would dismiss the appeal.

Also on the Blog

The Defence Toolkit – July 19, 2025: Crown discretion

This week's top three summaries: R v Varennes, 2025 SCC 22: #Crown discretion review, R v JN, 2025 ONSC 4041: #bad character, R v AC, 2025 ONSC...

The Defence Toolkit – July 12, 2025: Intoxication

This week's top three summaries: R v Crossley, 2025 BCCA 224: #intoxication & #murder, R v Khan, 2025 ABKB 357: s.9 #pill bottle, R v Barker,...

The Defence Toolkit – July 5, 2025: A Flashback

This week's top three summaries: R v Singh, 2025 ONCA 460: #omissions and #flashbacks, R v OW, 2025 ONSC 2922: #exclusive opportunity ID, R v Grant...

About Us

Working through your complex trial materials

Our lawyers have been litigating criminal trials and appeals for over 16 years in courtrooms throughout Canada. We can be of assistance to your practice. Whether you are looking for an appeal referral or some help with a complex written argument, our firm may be able to help. Our firm provides the following services available to other lawyers for referrals or contract work:

  1. Criminal Appeals
  2. Complex Criminal Litigation
  3. Ghostwriting Criminal Legal Briefs

Please review the rest of the website to see if our services are right for you.

Pawel Milczarek, Appellate Lawyer in Calgary, AB.

Written By Pawel Milczarek

Pawel is a partner at Sitar & Milczarek. When he’s not litigating he writes the Defence Toolkit blog.

Related Posts

The Defence Toolkit: February 15, 2024 – Role Play

The Defence Toolkit: February 15, 2024 – Role Play

This week's top three summaries: R v T.S., 2025 BCCA 25: #consent & role play, R v Khamvongsa, 2025 BCCA 33: 24(2) on s.8 breach and R v Stevenson, 2025 SKCA 13: DO #sentencing R v T.S., 2025 BCCA 25 [January 31, 2025] Sexual Assault: Role Play and Consent...

The Defence Toolkit – April 20, 2024: Blackout

The Defence Toolkit – April 20, 2024: Blackout

This week's top three summaries: R v Green, 2024 ABCA 118: #blackout and sex, R v TH, 2024 BCCA 123: CSO and appeal standard, and R v ADM, 2024 ABKB 212: #credibility and extrinsic facts. Our firm focuses on representation in complex criminal trials and criminal...